I | INTRODUCTION |
Aristotle (384-322 bc), Greek philosopher and scientist,
who shares with Plato and Socrates the distinction of being the most famous of
ancient philosophers.
Aristotle was born at Stagira, in Macedonia,
the son of a physician to the royal court. At the age of 17, he went to Athens
to study at Plato's Academy. He remained there for about 20 years, as a student
and then as a teacher.
When Plato died in 347 bc, Aristotle moved to Assos, a city in
Asia Minor, where a friend of his, Hermias, was ruler. There he counseled
Hermias and married his niece and adopted daughter, Pythias. After Hermias was
captured and executed by the Persians in 345 bc, Aristotle went to Pella, the
Macedonian capital, where he became the tutor of the king's young son Alexander,
later known as Alexander the Great. In 335, when Alexander became king,
Aristotle returned to Athens and established his own school, the Lyceum. Because
much of the discussion in his school took place while teachers and students were
walking about the Lyceum grounds, Aristotle's school came to be known as the
Peripatetic (“walking” or “strolling”) school. Upon the death of Alexander in
323 bc, strong anti-Macedonian
feeling developed in Athens, and Aristotle retired to a family estate in Euboea
(Évvoia). He died there the following year.
II | WORKS |
Aristotle, like Plato, made regular use of the
dialogue in his earliest years at the Academy, but lacking Plato's imaginative
gifts, he probably never found the form congenial. Apart from a few fragments in
the works of later writers, his dialogues have been wholly lost. Aristotle also
wrote some short technical notes, such as a dictionary of philosophic terms and
a summary of the doctrines of Pythagoras. Of these, only a few brief excerpts
have survived. Still extant, however, are Aristotle's lecture notes for
carefully outlined courses treating almost every branch of knowledge and art.
The texts on which Aristotle's reputation rests are largely based on these
lecture notes, which were collected and arranged by later editors.
Among the texts are treatises on logic, called
Organon (“instrument”), because they provide the means by which positive
knowledge is to be attained. His works on natural science include
Physics, which gives a vast amount of information on astronomy,
meteorology, plants, and animals. His writings on the nature, scope, and
properties of being, which Aristotle called First Philosophy (Protē
philosophia), were given the title Metaphysics in the first published
edition of his works (60? bc),
because in that edition they followed Physics. His treatment of the Prime
Mover, or first cause, as pure intellect, perfect in unity, immutable, and, as
he said, “the thought of thought,” is given in the Metaphysics. To his
son Nicomachus he dedicated his work on ethics, called the Nicomachean
Ethics. Other essential works include his Rhetoric, his
Poetics (which survives in incomplete form), and his Politics
(also incomplete).
III | METHODS |
Perhaps because of the influence of his
father's medical profession, Aristotle's philosophy laid its principal stress on
biology, in contrast to Plato's emphasis on mathematics. Aristotle regarded the
world as made up of individuals (substances) occurring in fixed natural kinds
(species). Each individual has its built-in specific pattern of development and
grows toward proper self-realization as a specimen of its type. Growth, purpose,
and direction are thus built into nature. Although science studies general
kinds, according to Aristotle, these kinds find their existence in particular
individuals. Science and philosophy must therefore balance, not simply choose
between, the claims of empiricism (observation and sense experience) and
formalism (rational deduction).
One of the most distinctive of Aristotle's
philosophic contributions was a new notion of causality. Each thing or event, he
thought, has more than one “reason” that helps to explain what, why, and where
it is. Earlier Greek thinkers had tended to assume that only one sort of cause
can be really explanatory; Aristotle proposed four. (The word Aristotle uses,
aition, “a responsible, explanatory factor” is not synonymous with the
word cause in its modern sense.)
These four causes are the material cause, the
matter out of which a thing is made; the efficient cause, the source of motion,
generation, or change; the formal cause, which is the species, kind, or type;
and the final cause, the goal, or full development, of an individual, or the
intended function of a construction or invention. Thus, a young lion is made up
of tissues and organs, its material cause; the efficient cause is its parents,
who generated it; the formal cause is its species, lion; and its final cause is
its built-in drive toward becoming a mature specimen. In different contexts,
while the causes are the same four, they apply analogically. Thus, the material
cause of a statue is the marble from which it was carved; the efficient cause is
the sculptor; the formal cause is the shape the sculptor realized—Hermes,
perhaps, or Aphrodite; and the final cause is its function, to be a work of fine
art.
In each context, Aristotle insists that
something can be better understood when its causes can be stated in specific
terms rather than in general terms. Thus, it is more informative to know that a
sculptor made the statue than to know that an artist made it; and even more
informative to know that Polycleitus chiseled it rather than simply that a
sculptor did so.
Aristotle thought his causal pattern was the
ideal key for organizing knowledge. His lecture notes present impressive
evidence of the power of this scheme.
IV | DOCTRINES |
Some of the principal aspects of Aristotle's
thought can be seen in the following summary of his doctrines, or theories.
A | Physics, or Natural Philosophy |
In astronomy, Aristotle proposed a finite,
spherical universe, with the earth at its center. The central region is made up
of four elements: earth, air, fire, and water. In Aristotle's physics, each of
these four elements has a proper place, determined by its relative heaviness,
its “specific gravity.” Each moves naturally in a straight line—earth down, fire
up—toward its proper place, where it will be at rest. Thus, terrestrial motion
is always linear and always comes to a halt. The heavens, however, move
naturally and endlessly in a complex circular motion. The heavens, therefore,
must be made of a fifth, and different element, which he called aither. A
superior element, aither is incapable of any change other than change of
place in a circular movement. Aristotle's theory that linear motion always takes
place through a resisting medium is in fact valid for all observable terrestrial
motions. He also held that heavier bodies of a given material fall faster than
lighter ones when their shapes are the same, a mistaken view that was accepted
as fact until the Italian physicist and astronomer Galileo conducted his
experiment with weights dropped from the Leaning Tower of Pisa.
B | Biology |
In zoology, Aristotle proposed a fixed set
of natural kinds (“species”), each reproducing true to type. An exception
occurs, Aristotle thought, when some “very low” worms and flies come from
rotting fruit or manure by “spontaneous generation.” The typical life cycles are
epicycles: The same pattern repeats, but through a linear succession of
individuals. These processes are therefore intermediate between the changeless
circles of the heavens and the simple linear movements of the terrestrial
elements. The species form a scale from simple (worms and flies at the bottom)
to complex (human beings at the top), but evolution is not possible.
C | Aristotelian Psychology |
For Aristotle, psychology was a study of
the soul. Insisting that form (the essence, or unchanging characteristic element
in an object) and matter (the common undifferentiated substratum of things)
always exist together, Aristotle defined a soul as a “kind of functioning of a
body organized so that it can support vital functions.” In considering the soul
as essentially associated with the body, he challenged the Pythagorean doctrine
that the soul is a spiritual entity imprisoned in the body. Aristotle's doctrine
is a synthesis of the earlier notion that the soul does not exist apart from the
body and of the Platonic notion of a soul as a separate, nonphysical entity.
Whether any part of the human soul is immortal, and, if so, whether its
immortality is personal, are not entirely clear in his treatise On the
Soul.
Through the functioning of the soul, the
moral and intellectual aspects of humanity are developed. Aristotle argued that
human insight in its highest form (nous poetikos, “active mind”) is not
reducible to a mechanical physical process. Such insight, however, presupposes
an individual “passive mind” that does not appear to transcend physical nature.
Aristotle clearly stated the relationship between human insight and the senses
in what has become a slogan of empiricism—the view that knowledge is grounded in
sense experience. “There is nothing in the intellect,” he wrote, “that was not
first in the senses.”
D | Ethics |
It seemed to Aristotle that the
individual's freedom of choice made an absolutely accurate analysis of human
affairs impossible. “Practical science,” then, such as politics or ethics, was
called science only by courtesy and analogy. The inherent limitations on
practical science are made clear in Aristotle's concepts of human nature and
self-realization. Human nature certainly involves, for everyone, a capacity for
forming habits; but the habits that a particular individual forms depend on that
individual's culture and repeated personal choices. All human beings want
“happiness,” an active, engaged realization of their innate capacities, but this
goal can be achieved in a multiplicity of ways.
Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics is an
analysis of character and intelligence as they relate to happiness. Aristotle
distinguished two kinds of “virtue,” or human excellence: moral and
intellectual. Moral virtue is an expression of character, formed by habits
reflecting repeated choices. A moral virtue is always a mean between two less
desirable extremes. Courage, for example, is a mean between cowardice and
thoughtless rashness; generosity, between extravagance and parsimony.
Intellectual virtues are not subject to this doctrine of the mean. Aristotle
argued for an elitist ethics: Full excellence can be realized only by the mature
male adult of the upper class, not by women, or children, or barbarians
(non-Greeks), or salaried “mechanics” (manual workers) for whom, indeed,
Aristotle did not want to allow voting rights.
In politics, many forms of human
association can obviously be found; which one is suitable depends on
circumstances, such as the natural resources, cultural traditions, industry, and
literacy of each community. Aristotle did not regard politics as a study of
ideal states in some abstract form, but rather as an examination of the way in
which ideals, laws, customs, and property interrelate in actual cases. He thus
approved the contemporary institution of slavery but tempered his acceptance by
insisting that masters should not abuse their authority, since the interests of
master and slave are the same. The Lyceum library contained a collection of 158
constitutions of the Greek and other states. Aristotle himself wrote the
Constitution of Athens as part of the collection, and after being lost,
this description was rediscovered in a papyrus copy in 1890. Historians have
found the work of great value in reconstructing many phases of the history of
Athens.
E | Logic |
In logic, Aristotle developed rules for
chains of reasoning that would, if followed, never lead from true premises to
false conclusions (validity rules). In reasoning, the basic links are
syllogisms: pairs of propositions that, taken together, give a new conclusion.
For example, “All humans are mortal” and “All Greeks are humans” yield the valid
conclusion “All Greeks are mortal.” Science results from constructing more
complex systems of reasoning. In his logic, Aristotle distinguished between
dialectic and analytic. Dialectic, he held, only tests opinions for their
logical consistency; analytic works deductively from principles resting on
experience and precise observation. This is clearly an intended break with
Plato's Academy, where dialectic was supposed to be the only proper method for
science and philosophy alike.
F | Metaphysics |
In his metaphysics, Aristotle argued for
the existence of a divine being, described as the Prime Mover, who is
responsible for the unity and purposefulness of nature. God is perfect and
therefore the aspiration of all things in the world, because all things desire
to share perfection. Other movers exist as well—the intelligent movers of the
planets and stars (Aristotle suggested that the number of these is “either 55 or
47”). The Prime Mover, or God, described by Aristotle is not very suitable for
religious purposes, as many later philosophers and theologians have observed.
Aristotle limited his “theology,” however, to what he believed science requires
and can establish.
V | INFLUENCE |
Aristotle's works were lost in the West after
the decline of Rome. During the 9th century ad, Arab scholars introduced Aristotle,
in Arabic translation, to the Islamic world (see Islam). The 12th-century
Spanish-Arab philosopher Averroës is the best known of the Arabic scholars who
studied and commented on Aristotle. In the 13th century, the Latin West renewed
its interest in Aristotle's work, and Saint Thomas Aquinas found in it a
philosophical foundation for Christian thought. Church officials at first
questioned Aquinas's use of Aristotle; in the early stages of its rediscovery,
Aristotle's philosophy was regarded with some suspicion, largely because his
teachings were thought to lead to a materialistic view of the world.
Nevertheless, the work of Aquinas was accepted, and the later philosophy of
scholasticism continued the philosophical tradition based on Aquinas's
adaptation of Aristotelian thought.
The influence of Aristotle's philosophy has
been pervasive; it has even helped to shape modern language and common sense.
His doctrine of the Prime Mover as final cause played an important role in
theology. Until the 20th century, logic meant Aristotle's logic. Until the
Renaissance, and even later, astronomers and poets alike admired his concept of
the universe. Zoology rested on Aristotle's work until British scientist Charles
Darwin modified the doctrine of the changelessness of species in the 19th
century. In the 20th century a new appreciation has developed of Aristotle's
method and its relevance to education, literary criticism, the analysis of human
action, and political analysis.
Not only the discipline of zoology, but also
the world of learning as a whole, seems to amply justify Darwin's remark that
the intellectual heroes of his own time “were mere schoolboys compared to old
Aristotle.”
No comments:
Post a Comment